Saturday, August 25, 2012

The English Individualists as They Appear in Liberty*


by Carl Watner

1982

The leading English individualists as they appear in Benjamin Tucker's journal, Liberty, are Auberon Herbert, Wordsworth Donisthorpe, Joseph Hiam Levy, Joseph Greevz Fisher, John Badcock, Jr., Albert Tarn, and Henry Seymour. Ranked approximately according to their contributions and involvement in Liberty, this group also includes M. D. O'Brien, J. M. Armsden, W. C. Crofts, A. E. Porter and J. C. Spence.[1]Their activities and writings serve as the focal point for research into the history of late-nineteenth and early-twentieth century individualist anarchism in England.Liberty, an international clearinghouse for libertarian ideas during the almost three decades of its existence (1881-1908), reported on and editorialized about the ideology and politics of the English individualist movement.The purpose of this paper is to bring to light some of the little known history and ideas of the movement, based on articles in Liberty and other sources.


The English individualist anarchist movement was no more or less unified than its ideological counterpart in the United States.Auberon Herbert (1838-1906), a one-time member of Parliament, called his philosophy "voluntaryism" and was the world's leading advocate of voluntary taxation.For over a decade, he edited and published an individualist journal, called Free Life.One of his supporters, M. D. O'Brien, went to jail for refusing to send his children to school.[2] Wordsworth Donisthorpe (1847-?) was a near-anarchist barrister and small-time coal mine owner, who, with his cousin, W. C. Crofts (1846-1894), formed the State Resistance Union in 1880.He edited a journal called Jus, and his organization was the forerunner of The Liberty and Property Defence League.Joseph Hiam Levy (1838-1913) was a teacher of economics at Birkbeck College and became involved with the Personal Rights Association in 1878. He eventually became secretary of this organization and edited its journals for many years.Levy was the leading individualist advocate of limited government with compulsory rights of taxation. He was also involved in the anti-vivisection movement.J. Greevz Fisher, John Badcock, Henry Seymour, and J. H. Levy were all involved in the Legitimation League formed in London around 1892 for the purpose of changing the bastardy laws so that offspring born out of wedlock were not deprived of their rightful inheritances.Fisher formed the Parents' Defence League, whose apparent purpose was to passively resist compulsory schooling of children.[3]Although little else is known about Fisher, he was a clear economic thinker, as his contributions to Liberty demonstrate. He presented one of the two known refutations of money-crankism during the nineteenth century.[4]John Badcock, Jr. (1861?-1926) was an egoist and follower of the doctrines of Max Stirner.He was an accountant by profession and later became a dealer in Chinese art.[5]Albert Tarn was one of Tucker's agents for Liberty in England.He published the Herald of Anarchy and Free Trade magazines during the early 1890's.[6]Henry Seymour, John Armsden, and Badcock were associated in the Free Currency Propaganda movement, which advocated repeal of the Bank Charter Act of 1844, repeal of the legal tender laws, and destroying the Bank of England's monopoly hold on the money supply.By increasing the supply of money in circulation, the propagandists hoped to lower the rate of interest and diminish the capitalists' profits.Their ideas on interest, and on the causes of poverty, wealth, and capital were well outlined in contributions appearing in Liberty. Henry Seymour was a free-thinker and friend of Charles Bradlaugh. In the mid-1880's he published a journal called The Anarchist, and was well acquainted with the London anarchists of all persuasions.
This disparate group of activists and thinkers were truly individualists; no two were wholly alike in their philosophy.What united them was their general adherence to a doctrine of individual freedom in economic enterprise and social relations, which they believed should not be restricted by governmental regulations.Every one of the group mentioned had at least minor differences with Tucker and the editorial doctrines of Liberty.Although some of the English individualists refused to call themselves anarchists, their doctrines were perilously close to anarchism.Benjamin Tucker defined anarchism as the doctrine that the State should be abolished and all the affairs of men be carried out on a voluntary basis.[7]More than likely, Herbert, Donisthorpe, Tarn, Seymour, and Badcock would have accepted this statement as an expression of their own political beliefs. J. H. Levy definitely would not.
In an appendix on "Political Terminology" appearing in his debate with Herbert on Taxation and Anarchism, Levy charted out the differences among the English individualists.Both the communist anarchist and the individualistic anarchist, wrote Levy, are "opposed to the existence of government; and, though they differ as to what should be done when the State had been got rid of, and would probably be at each other's throat the moment the authority which they both assail was removed, the range of their agreement entitled them equally to the general designation of Anarchists."[8]True individualism, according to Levy, asserts that "compulsory co-operation is good up to the point at which freedom is maximized," and that "it is harmful when pushed beyond that point.It affirms that government can promote happiness only by maintaining the widest practicable liberty, which it regards as the political--as distinguished from the ethical--summum bonum; and it judges all political measures by their tendency to promote or impede the attainment of this end."[9]Referring indirectly to Herbert, Levy claimed that no individualist would ever dub himself an anarchist, "though some Anarchists call themselves Individualists."[10]
The main bone of contention between Herbert and Levy was illustrated in their exchange of views in Taxation and Anarchism, which appeared as a publication of The Personal Rights Association in 1912, several years after Herbert's death.This discussion between Levy and Herbert was the out-growth of a speech delivered by Levy in January 1890, entitled "The Outcome of Individualism," and of his contributions to the Personal Rights Journal of October 1890. Levy attacked "the whole scheme of so-called 'Voluntary Taxation"' because it seems to show a "deficiency of analytic power."
Its projectors appear to think that they can substitute for the State an organization supported by voluntary contributions. . . . Taxation must be, potentially at least, co-extensive with government.The way to reduce it is severely to limit the functions of government to the maximizing of liberty, to abolish privilege, and to exercise due vigilance over the expenditure of State revenue.Such vigilance is becoming every day farther removed from possibility by the growth in complexity of the functions assigned to the State. This is the evil which must be attacked."[11]
Herbert opened his attack on Levy by rebutting Levy's challenge that "voluntary taxation" was a contradiction in terms.He claimed that Levy's use of the concept "compulsory co-operation" was an even "greater" contradiction. Summarizing his position, Herbert argued as follows:
What I contend for is that no force-system should over-ride the consent of a man who has not aggressed against the person or property of his neighbour. I say that a man's consent as regards his own actions is the most sacred thing in the world, and the one foundation on which all human relations must be built.To me it seems idle to talk of Individualism where this consent is not held sacred. . . [T]he moment I am told that the individual may be caught by the collar and compelled to form a society, may he compelled to share in making laws, may be compelled to maintain these laws, I feel that I am no longer standing on Individualistic ground. . . . Believing, then, that the judgment of every individual who has not himself aggressed against his neighbour is supreme as regards his own actions, and that this is the rock on which Individualism rests--I deny that A and B can go to C and force him to form a State and extract from him certain payments and services in the name of such State. . . . The only difference between the tax-compelling Individualist and the State-Socialist is that whilst they both have vested the ownership of C in A and B, the tax-compelling Individualist proposes to use the powers of ownership in a very limited fashion, the Socialist in a very complete fashion.I object to the ownership in any fashion.[12]
Responding to Herbert's arguments, Levy maintained that Herbert was mounting "an Anarchistic attack on Individualism." "It is a direct confirmation of my statement that voluntary taxationists have fallen into Anarchism without knowing it."[13]Victor Yarros, in his editorial capacity with Liberty, confirmed Levy's judgment in this matter by arguing: "Voluntaryism is simply Mr. Herbert's preferred synonym for Individualistic Anarchism."[14]
The discussion between Levy and Herbert largely revolved around the way in which each formulated his view of individualism.Herbert held that compulsory taxation was opposed to the principles of individualism, to such an extent that the two could never be reconciled in any satisfactory way.Herbert was quite prepared to offer a philosophic basis for individualism from the anti-taxationist point of view:
(1). The great natural fact of each person being born in possession of a separate mind and separate body implies the ownership of such mind and body by each person, and rights of direction over such mind and body; it will be found on examination that no other deduction is reasonable.
(2). Such self-ownership implies the restraint of violent or fraudulent aggressions made upon it.
(3). Individuals, therefore, have the right to protect themselves by force against such aggressions made forcibly or fraudulently, and they may delegate such acts of self-defence to a special body, called a government. . .
Condensed into a few words, our Voluntaryist formula would run: "The sovereignty of the individual must retain intact, except where the individual coerced has aggressed upon the sovereignty of another unaggressive individual."[l5]
Interestingly enough, Levy flatly rejected this formulation of individualism. Levy asserted: "It seems to me that Mr. Herbert has wandered into the cloud land of meta-politics. . . . I certainly shall not accept such a 'philosophical basis for Individualism,' because 'no other deduction' of the same sort 'is reasonable.'There is no deduction at all, but a gross and palpable petitio principii. "[16]In short, Levy concluded that "Mr. Herbert's formula is that of Anarchism."[17]
Herbert rejected Levy's claim that he was an anarchist.According to his own understanding, anarchists would not retain any form of organization to repress aggression or crime.They would not maintain any sort of defense agencies to function as police or courts.The difference between him and Levy was that while he would retain such organization in his ideal society, he would not force those disapproving of the police or courts to pay for them; Mr. Levy, in contrast, would compel the conscientious objectors to pay for them just the same.[18]"We agree that there must be a central agency to deal with crime--an agency that defends the liberty of all men, and employs force against the uses of force; hut my central agency rests upon voluntary support, whilst Mr. Levy's central agency rests on compulsory support."[19]The question between Levy and Herbert, as Herbert saw it, was: "Are the principles of Individualism most truly followed when the tax for the support of this [central] agency is taken voluntarily or compulsorily?"[20]
Viewing himself not as an anarchist but as an individualist, Herbert maintained that in an anarchistic society no such central agency for the repression of crimes and aggressions could exist."My charge against Anarchism is that it sees many forms of crime existing in the world, and it refuses to come to any settled opinion as to what it will do in the matter.If it says it will do nothing, then we must live under the reign of the murderer, tempered by Judge Lynch; if it says it will have some form of local jury, then we are back into government again at once.[21]Herbert acknowledged that there were existing schools of anarchism, "represented in America by Mr. Tucker, and some philosophical Anarchists in England," but as far as he could see, "none of these schools are prepared to tell us clearly what they will do about ordinary crime."It was Herbert's contention that "the moment they begin to deal with crime according to any fixed method and settled precedent, they are at once back into Archism."[22]The dividing line between statism and anarchism was, according to Herbert: "Do you intend to provide an agency for dealing with crime according to fixed rules and methods, or not? The way in which you pay your agency--though a very important matter in itself, must be looked upon as a non-essential element in the difference between the two systems."[23]As Herbert saw it, the anarchists espoused no fixed or objective standards by which to repress crime and aggression."[24]
Levy, for his part, was a perceptive critic.Barring confusion over the labels "individualism" and "anarchism." Levy realized that taxation was the very essence of government as it had always existed."A voluntary association for defence could exist without it; but such an association would not be government.''[25] Nor could he accept Herbert's analysis of the essential distinction between individualism and anarchism as being based on whether or not a central agency of defense was retained in their respective ideal societies. Levy rightly claimed "that there is nothing in Anarchism to prevent those who hold it from retaining any sort of organization for the repression of invasive conduct, so long as that organization is a voluntary one; and in this proviso they do not differ from Mr. Herbert."[26] Levy maintained that Herbert had not thought out the consequences of his doctrine.What would happen, he asked, if one group of people in a voluntary taxationist society declined to recognize the "definition of rights promulgated by this voluntary association in which they took no part. . . ?"Suppose such a group "endeavored to set up a rival association of their own, . . .what would he do?"[27]
Would he [Herbert] prevent the formation of any such association?If so, does not this mean compulsory submission to the dictates of the association patronized by him?And if he would not interfere with the establishment of rival associations of this kind, with different views from his own association as to rights and methods, this would only defer for a little time the overruling of the weaker party. Where the ideas of such rival organizations clashed there would be conflict. The effective minority would be subdued in one way or another, and for all practical purposes they would be compelled to co-operate with the effective majority or to submit to it.[28]
As we shall see, Levy, the individualist, threw at Herbert the same arguments as those raised by the anarchist critics of his idea of voluntary taxation.
Herbert was wrong in viewing anarchism as not allowing for the existence of competing defense agencies to repress and fight crime.There was, however, an element of truth in his criticism of the individualistic anarchist movement of his day.Tucker, for example, maintained that local juries could render judicial decisions and claimed that anarchists viewed the functions of government as they would any other economic service provided by the market.Competing agencies would provide defense services, such as police protection and court decisions, on a voluntary and competitive basis.Where Herbert was correct in his criticisms of Tucker and other contemporary anarchists was that they failed to specify that all such competing defense agencies would be bound by a rational and objective code of libertarian legal principles and procedures based on the defense of person and property.[29]
Levy was correct in asserting that Herbert had not thought through the problems of voluntary taxation.Although coming from different perspectives, both Levy and Herbert's anarchist critics, such as Rothbard, ask of Herbert and the proponents of voluntary taxation: "Would they use force to compel people not to use a freely competing defense agency within the same geographic area?"As Rothbard writes: "The voluntary taxationists have never attempted to answer this problem; they have rather stubbornly assumed that no one would set up a competing defense agency within a State's territorial limits."[30] Clearly, if the government of a voluntary taxation society chose to outlaw all competing defense agencies, it would not function as the voluntary society sought by its proponents."It would not force payment of taxes," but it would monopolize the provision of defense services."On the other hand, if the government did permit free competition in defense service, there would soon no longer be a central government over the territory.Defense agencies, police and judicial, would compete with one another in the same uncoerced manner as the producers of any other service on the market. . . . Defense service would at last be made fully marketable"[31]
Despite these flaws in his theory, Herbert realized that Levy's theory of individualism was marred by the existence of compulsory taxation in a society trying to maximize freedom.Herbert understood that compulsion was a contradictory element in such a society and that taxation had to be eliminated.However Herbert erred in not realizing that "freely competing judicial agencies would have to be guided by a body of absolute law to enable them to distinguish objectively between defense and invasion."[32]This point was not crystal clear even to Tucker or his followers, although at one point Tucker declared that "Anarchism does mean exactly the observance and enforcement of the natural law of liberty."[33]It was left up to the twentieth-century individualist anarchists to explain the importance of a libertarian legal code. For example, Rothbard posits that his view of libertarianism includes, "not only the abolition of the State, but also the general adoption of a libertarian law code."If the bulk of the population were to become persuaded to abolish the State, then they must already have been convinced that the aggressions the State commits are immoral violations of liberty and private property: "on what other basis can we convince them to abolish their revered government apparatus?"[34]
In the various discussions of voluntary taxation which appeared in Liberty, Tucker came very close to espousing this viewpoint.In response to a series of queries from Donisthorpe, Tucker noted: "A system of Anarchy in actual operation implies a previous education of the people in the principles of Anarchy, and that in turn implies such a distrust and hatred of interference that the only band of voluntary cooperators which could gain sufficient support to enforce its will would be that which either entirely refrained from interference or reduced it to a minimum."[35]Although he did not follow up on this insight, Tucker realized that the implementation of anarchy carried with it the implication that people generally understood and accepted a libertarian legal code.
In other discussions of voluntary taxation with the English individualists, Tucker threw out a series of challenges to his correspondents. In Liberty of November 1, 1890, around the same time that Levy and Herbert were beginning to exchange views, Tucker reprinted several paragraphs written by Levy in the Personal Rights Journal.In these paragraphs, Levy plainly stated that anarchism implies the right of an individual to stand aside and see a man murdered or a woman raped. In contrast, Levy asserted that individualism would not only restrain the active invader but would also coerce into cooperation the man who would otherwise be a passive witness of aggression.Tucker accepted this judgment and pointed out that to coerce the peaceful non-cooperator is to violate the law of equal liberty.It is just as "impossible to attain the maximum of liberty by depriving people of their liberty as to attain the maximum of wealth by depriving people of their wealth. . . . [T]he means is absolutely destructive of the end." Tucker understood that with compulsory taxation abolished, there could be no State."The defensive institution that will succeed it will be steadily deterred from becoming an invasive institution through fear that the voluntary contributions will fall off.This constant motive for a voluntary defensive institution to keep itself trimmed down to the popular demand is itself the best possible safeguard against the bugbear of multitudinous rival political agencies."Tucker concluded his editorial by citing his chief interest in Levy's article. Tucker was excited by Levy's "valid criticism of those Individualists who accept voluntary taxation but stop short, or think they stop short of Anarchism, and I shall wait with much curiosity to see what Mr. Greevz Fisher, and especially Mr. Auberon Herbert, will have to say in reply. Mr. Donisthorpe probably will he heard from also, but he really does not fall within Mr. Levy's criticism.He is, as Mr. Levy says, more of an Anarchist than anything else. . . . On the whole Anarchists have more reason to be grateful to Mr. Levy for his article than to complain of it. It is at least an appeal for intellectual consistency on this subject, and as such it renders unquestionable service to the cause of plumb-line Anarchism."[36]
Four issues later, Tucker published a letter from Donisthorpe to the editor of Free Life, which he captioned "Discrepant Boundaries." In the letter, Donisthorpe claimed that he saw no contradiction in the expression "voluntary taxation."Addressing Auberon Herbert, Donisthorpe wrote:
My quarrel with your Individualism is that the world is not ready for it. My individualism is absolute Anarchy qualified by a regard for social evolution. . . . Mr. Levy seems to me to hold with us moderate Anarchists that at present we require a residuum of State action.But where I think he errs is in supposing that this is the necessary and permanent condition.In the perfect (or more perfect) state of social development, I agree with your view.In the present state Mr. Levy and I are more in line, looking on the State as a necessary institution. We diverge when he insists on regarding it as a permanent institution. Perhaps I should even outrun you a little in the future.I am inclined to think with Tucker, that even the administration of justice will fall into private hands, though it is hard to foresee the construction of the judicial system." [37]
Several months later, Tucker published another article taken from Herbert's Free Life entitled "Justice and Taxation" and written by one of Herbert's associates, M. D. O'Brien.In it, O'Brien set forth both his and Herbert's view of voluntary taxation.Opening on the note that all individualists are in agreement that it is right to restrain by force the man who aggresses by force upon another man, O'Brien chided the "Taxation-Individualists" ("to use a 'Free Life' term") for thinking it right to coerce a peaceful non-invader.In agreement with O'Brien, Tucker wrote:
a man's non-aggressive earnings are his own, and there is no other warrant, save force, for a majority confiscating any portion of them . . . . We are only justified in using force when force is used to us, and all the helpers we get should be volunteers, not people whom we have impressed, or, what is the same thing, the impressed earnings of those people.[38]
In a much earlier piece (which was subsequently reprinted in Instead of a Book, Tucker referred to "some very interesting and valuable discussion" which "is going on in the London Jus concerning the question of compulsory versus voluntary taxation."F. W. Read had written to Donisthorpe, editor of Jus, that voluntary taxation implied the existence of five or six voluntary states in England. Tucker pointed out that he saw nothing wrong or unusual with such a situation.After all, Tucker explained, there were more than five or six churches in England and many more than five or six insurance companies."Though Mr. Read has grasped one idea of the voluntary taxationists," he failed to see the other important idea behind it: "the idea that defence is a service, like any other service; that it is labor both useful and desired, and therefore an economic commodity subject to the law of supply and demand; . . .that, competition prevailing, patronage would go to those who furnished the best article at the lowest price; that the production and sale of this commodity are now monopolized by the State; that the State, like almost all monopolists, charges exorbitant prices; that, like almost all monopolists, it supplies a worthless or nearly worthless, article; . . .the State takes advantage of its monopoly of defence to furnish invasion instead of protection; . . .and, finally, that the State exceeds all its fellow-monopolists in the extent of its villainy because it enjoys the unique privilege of compelling all people to buy its product whether they want it or not."Tucker concluded that only by five or six "states" hanging out their shingles and competing with one another could people be assured of quality service at reasonable rates."And what is more,--the better their services, the less they would he needed; so that the multiplication of 'States' involves the abolition of the State.''[39]
As we have seen, the editors of Jus, Personal Rights, Free Life, and Liberty had significant differences among themselves. Levy commented on this in his previously mentioned discussion on "Political Terminology."With respect to land ownership, Levy called Herbert a conservative anarchist."The Conservative Anarchist would retain private property in land very much as it is in England at the present day, merely abolishing the obstacles to its free sale and purchase.The Individualist Anarchist would laugh at this pretension to sell or let land and would recognize only the right of the squatter to the land in his use or productive occupation." The communist anarchist would decline to recognize any rights of property in land.[40]Liberty's and Tucker's position was that of the individualist anarchist, advocating the doctrine of occupation and use as the sole basis for land-holding.[41]Levy's position on landownership is not clearly spelled out, although Tucker claimed that he was an advocate of land nationalization in England.[42]
These differences regarding landownership were aired in the pages of Liberty many times over.In one of the earlier references in Liberty, referring to the "Solutions of the Land Problem" and the English individualists, Victor Yarros noted that although he agreed with Auberon Herbert's conclusions as far as they went, he did not reach these conclusions by the same logic.Quoting from an 1889 symposium on the land question held by the Personal Rights Association, Yarros quoted Herbert as follows: "The free and open market is the one system that does most justice among individuals, being the only impartial institution that exists, and at the same time is the only system that gives the evolutionary forces free play. . . . I scarcely need add that at present we have not a truly free and open market for land.All artificial impediments should be removed, and no new ones invented."[43] Related issues were raised in Liberty about a year later, when Tucker reprinted correspondence which had appeared in Free Life.Albert Tarn, whom Tucker describes as an "Anarchistic correspondent," had addressed a letter to Free Life in which he tried to combat Herbert's assertion that anarchism would throw property titles, especially land titles, into hopeless confusion. Herbert's contention was that "under the law of the free market, everybody knows, first, who owns a particular piece of property, and, secondly, the conditions under which property can be acquired." Herbert attacked the doctrine of occupancy and use for being vague and indefinite in terms of establishing how ownership would be established and transferred in an anarchist society.Editorializing, Tucker rejoined that it would be up to "municipalities" (based on voluntary associations) to "formulate and enforce this view" of occupancy and use.According to Tucker, "under Anarchism all rules and laws will be little more than suggestions for the guidance of juries, and that all disputes, whether about land or anything else, will be submitted to juries which will judge not only the facts but the law."[44]
Several months later, under the headline "Private Property and Freedom," Victor Yarros picked up the argument again.According to Yarros, the difference between the viewpoints of Liberty and Mr. Herbert was: "he believes in allowing people to retain all their possessions, no matter how unjustly and basely acquired, while getting them, so to speak, to swear off stealing and usurping and to promise to behave well in the future.We, on the other hand, while insisting on the principle of private property, in wealth honestly obtained under the reign of liberty, do not think it either unjust or unwise to dispossess the landlords who have monopolized natural wealth by force and fraud.We hold that the poor and disinherited toilers would be justified in expropriating, not alone the landlords, who notoriously have no equitable titles to their lands, but all the financial lords and rulers, all the millionaires and very wealthy individuals."Yarros recognized that "almost all possessors of great wealth enjoy neither what they nor their ancestors rightfully acquired (and if Mr. Herbert wishes to challenge the correctness of this statement, we are ready to go with him into full discussion of the subject).If he holds that the landlords are justly entitled to their lands, let him make a defence of the landlords or an attack on our unjust proposal."[45]Unfortunately, Herbert never defended his position in Liberty. In the following issue, however, Tucker printed another letter from Herbert in which he continued his attack on occupancy and use. Tucker commented on it as follows:
The trouble with Mr. Herbert is that he begs the question of property altogether, and insists on treating the land problem as if it were simply a question of buying and selling and lending and borrowing, to be settled simply by the open market.Here I meet him with the words of his more conservative brother in Individualism, Mr. J. H. Levy, editor of the "Personal Rights Journal," who is trying to show Mr. Herbert that he ought to call himself an Anarchist instead of an Individualist. Mr. Levy says, and I say after him: "When we come to the ethical basis of property, Mr. Herbert refers us to the open market.But this is an evasion. The question is not whether we should he able to sell or acquire in the open market anything which we rightfully possess, but how we come into rightful possession.And if men differ on this, as they do most emphatically, how is this to be settled?"[46]
Auberon Herbert was a hybrid, fully acceptable neither to Levy, the individualist, nor to Tucker, the anarchist.Even Wordsworth Donisthorpe rejected Herbert's notions of self-ownership and rights: "Mr. Auberon Herbert insists on the right of self-ownership.He claims the right to own himself.I dispute it.I cannot see upon what the right is based. . . . I saw the force of their [the abolitionists'] arguments, and agreed; not because the niggers had any right to their liberty, but because I thought that in my interest that right should be conferred upon them.I deny the right then claimed for them, and I am delighted that they enjoy it now."[47]Yet, Herbert was not without his supporters (except perhaps on the property or self-ownership question). John Badcock, in a letter to the Personal Rights Journal, wrote: "The most valuable part of Auberon Herbert's teaching, to my mind, is the destruction which he gives to the artificial distinctions that have been set up between the acts of government and the acts of individuals, and the placing on par of all aggressions, whether individually or collectively perpetrated, whether sanctified by statute law or not so sanctified."[48]
Herbert's differences with Tucker and Liberty were not limited to property matters alone.Within a year after he had serialized and reprinted Herbert's A Politician in Sight of Haven, Tucker chastised Herbert for not realizing the importance of economic equity to anarchist thinking. "Mr. Herbert proves beyond question that the government of man by man is utterly without justification, but is quite ignorant of the fact that interest, rent, and profits will find no place in the perfect economic order."Tucker's comments not only illustrate his own economic thinking, but criticize Herbert at the same time. Tucker complained that Herbert had never called attention to the importance of free trade in banking: "If he would only dwell upon the evils of the money-issuing monopoly and emphasize with his great power the fact that competition, in this as in other matters, would give us all that is needed of the best possible article at the lowest possible price, thereby steadily reducing interest and rent to zero, putting capital within the comfortable reach of all deserving and enterprising people, and causing the greatest liberation on record of heretofore restricted energies."[49]
In turn, Herbert eventually asked in his Free Life how Tucker could justify a campaign against the right of men to lend and borrow.Tucker, of course, denied that he had ever campaigned on such an issue, but pointed out that he hoped that lending and borrowing might one day disappear in an anarchist society, where there would be no restrictions on people monetizing their own credit.Tucker asserted that "interest, however it may have originated, exists today only by virtue of the legal monopoly of the use of credit for currency purposes." Anarchists "trace the process by which an abolition of that monopoly would reduce the rate of interest to zero. Mr. Herbert never stops to analyze this process that he may find the weak spot in it and point it out; he simply declares that interest, instead of resting on monopoly, is the natural, inevitable outcome of human convenience and the open market. . . . If it be true that interest will exist in the absence of monopoly, then there is some flaw in the reasoning by which the Anarchists argue from the abolition of monopoly to the disappearance of interest."[50]
The pages of Liberty were peppered with arguments over economic issues, especially those issues concerned with money, banking, and interest. There were disputations in all directions: American anarchists arguing with other Americans; Americans arguing with the English individualists; and even the English individualists using the pages of the American Liberty to dispute among themselves.Of the English individualists, J. Greevz Fisher was probably the most prolific writer on these topics. Fisher was embroiled in at least three sets of debates appearing in Liberty.Beginning in 1891, Fisher and Tucker engaged in a spirited exchange concerning the power of government over values and free trade in banking.This exchange was included in Instead of a Book.Then in 1894 Hugo Bilgram and Fisher had it out in a lengthy series of letters regarding the justification of interest. Finally, in late 1896 and early 1897, John Badcock and Fisher went at one another over the alleged money famine and the value and volume of money.In most of these debates, Fisher criticized the anarchists from the point of view of sound economics.[51]
In the first of these series of debates, Tucker and Fisher discussed the merits of mutual banking.Fisher maintained that there was no legal obstacle to the introduction and circulation of promises of all types (such as promises to deliver wheat, cotton, or oil) which might then take the place of the Bank of England promises which circulated as money.Since there was no restriction on the types of money that might circulate, along with gold and promises to pay gold, Fisher claimed that government, in general, had little power to affect the purchasing power of gold.Tucker, on the other hand, alleged that the laws of England did not allow the workingmen to form mutual banks; that is, banks designed to issue paper money against any property that it may see fit to accept as security and such money not being redeemable in gold or silver.If mutual banks were not outlawed, then Tucker suggested that his English compatriots had nothing to complain of in the way of finance and had only to go out and start up their own banks in order to monetize their own credit.Tucker was convinced that such banking institutions were illegal in England "and in that case I tell him again that the present value of gold is a monopoly value sustained by the exclusive monetary privilege given it by the government."[52]
In his rebuttal, Fisher asserted: "Schemes to bring about the abolition of interest, especially when the authors promulgate this as a necessary consequence of free trade in banking are pernicious. . . . What is called free trade in banking actually means only unlimited liberty to create debt.It is the erroneous labelling of debt as money which begets most of the fallacies of the currency-fadists."[53]Tucker responded by quoting from Colonial William Greene's Mutual Banking, claiming that mutual banking would reduce the value of gold because "it would thereby be stripped of that exclusive monetary utility conferred upon it by the State."Tucker added that "the percentage of this reduction no one can tell in advance, any more than he can tell how much whiskey would fall in price if there were unrestricted competition in the sale of it."[54]In his third letter in this series of exchanges, Fisher restated his contention that Tucker was wrong in thinking that the law of England did not permit mutual banks. In Fisher's opinion, the concern of Tucker and the American anarchists was misplaced because they greatly overestimated the evils of the State banking system.[55]
In 1893 Tucker reprinted an address delivered by Hugo Bilgram on the subject of interest: "Is Interest Just?"In turn, J. Greevz Fisher wrote the Manchester Times criticizing Bilgram's presentation. The following year Liberty carried a letter from Bilgram answering Fisher's attack.[56]This was the beginning of a lengthy exchange between these two correspondents. Tucker would publish a letter by Fisher and in the same issue Bilgram's "rejoinder" would appear. Fisher claimed that "the hire of tools, materials, and maintenance would yield a revenue in the absence of money" and that it was not the existence of government and its restrictive monetary policies that were responsible for interest."What is necessary in order to establish the justice of interest is to show that in the absence of any restriction upon the issue of instruments of credit, and in the utter absence of laws of legal tender, interest would still be paid." Mr. Bilgram, on his part, contended that government policies, such as "legal regulation of the volume of currency," are "the cause of crises and business stagnation, of the existence of squalid poverty among those unable to find employment."[57]In Fisher's next letter to Liberty he outlined the core of his arguments against Bilgram:
Free and wholly unrestricted issue of all sorts of paper by all sorts of people to the utmost extent to which they could get it into circulation would certainly have as one of its results the development of a greater caution in accepting promises from those calling themselves bankers, and the elaboration of a system of voluntary audits and mutual guarantee of each other's notes by many of these bankers. . . . Mr. Bilgram appears to take no notice of the argument that the rate of interest upon loans. . .[would still exist] under a system of barter. . . . Interest is the hire of commodities separated from their owner and entrusted to another person.The time of separation is a privation to one party (in marginal cases, which rule all cases) and a benefit to the other party.[58]
In later letters, Fisher stressed the importance of understanding the purchasing power of money.As he phrased it, "As money becomes scarce, it becomes more potent in exact proportion to its rise in value."[59] Bilgram admitted that to the extent that interest "is a payment for risk. . .interest is just," but he continued to assail "as unjust that part of interest which is said to be paid for being 'deprived of a day's pleasure'.''[60]In Bilgram's view, interest was a monopoly privilege created by the laws forbidding the circulation of banknotes other than those by legally recognized banks.Thus interest was paid to holders of these notes only because of this exclusive monopoly privilege, which in effect restricted the amount of currency in circulation and on loan.Although Tucker was sympathetic to Bilgram's arguments, he left it to his readers "to judge between the arguments that have been advanced," when this debate closed in 1895.[61]
While these arguments were appearing in Liberty, several of the English individualists in London organized a new movement which they termed "The Free Currency Propaganda."The society was formed for the purpose of assaulting the monopoly of money-issue.Their prospectus set forth the following views:
We affirm that the equitable payment of labor. . .is its entire product. . .and that the prevailing monstrous departure from this self-evident principle of justice, the sole and sufficient cause of social discontent and oppression, is due to the monopolies of land and capital. . . . We furthermore affirm that the monopoly of capital is solely due to the monopoly of monetary credit, which necessarily and essentially results from the arbitrary and exclusive adoption of gold--or specie--value as the basis of the circulating medium. . . . The tyranny of the money monopoly thus operates not only positively by exacting the tribute of interest and monopoly profits, but also negatively by barring the working classes from self-help and association.[62]
Among the names appearing at the end of this prospectus were those of Henry Seymour, John Armsden, Alfred E. Porter and John Badcock, Jr. Although J. Greevz Fisher could not support The Free Currency Propaganda movement, he realized that there was an element of truth in its assertions. He could support the idea of "free banking" based on property rights as summed up by G. O. Warren, writing under the name of T. L. M'Cready, one of the founding members of the movement: "the right to private property necessarily includes the right to exchange that property, and the right to exchange it includes the right to determine what it shall be exchanged for, be it any article or commodity, or a piece of paper with an inscription on it, be that inscription written or printed, and from whatever source. And, therefore, that any restriction upon, or interference with, exchange is a denial of the right of private property, and should be resisted."[63]
In 1896 John Badcock, Jr. wrote an article appearing in Liberty on "The Money Famine" in which he supported these ideas. The main thrust of his argument was to oppose State monopolization of money issuance: "Let us have free trade in the issue of money. Only under freedom can the merits or demerits of any particular monies and instruments of credit have a chance to be demonstrated, and the fittest survive.Good money may be left to drive out bad money unaided.Let it be unhindered."[64]However, his argument was not limited to this point.Badcock considered that there was a true "money famine" caused by restrictive banking laws and legal tender laws and, much like Bilgram, claimed that if the supply of money were increased interests, profits, and rent would disappear. In his first of a series of attacks on these ideas, which Tucker printed soon after the appearance of Badcock's original article, Fisher maintained that the "money famine" was allegation rather than fact. He termed the expectation that interest, profits, and rent would disappear under a regime of free banking as "positively puerile." "Under complete monetary freedom the delusion that debts are money would vanish.The benefits to be expected [from complete monetary freedom] lie in the direction of increased activity, competition, and stability of bankers, money-lenders, and borrowers."[65] He also stressed the importance of understanding that the quantity of money in circulation was not of paramount concern because the purchasing power of money was not fixed and was changeable in accord with the supply of money on the market.The discussions and rejoinders between Badcock and Fisher continued in several later issues of Liberty and revolved around the formation of mutual banks in England and the exact form which the notes of such banks might take.This exchange ended finally in April 1897.[66]
None of these arguments was ever settled once and for all in Liberty. More than two years after the Badcock-Fisher debate, in September 1899, Wordsworth Donisthorpe sent a letter to Tucker on "Currency; Money and Credit; Coinage."[67]Not to be outdone, Fisher addressed a letter to Liberty on "Mr. Donisthorpe on Currency." This was his last contribution to Liberty on the subject of money.In it he made two very interesting observations. First, he supported the arguments of those advocating perfect freedom to issue money."Liberty would enable the markets and force the issuers [of money] automatically and continuously to correct and improve the money or tokens.Gresham's law as to the superior potency of inferior money applies only to fiat made money."[68] Secondly, he summarized his views on the significance of monetary freedom in England, should it be instituted sometime in the future:
What then would be the advantages of liberty in relation to the currency? They would be great, but not at all overwhelming.They could only remedy evils which exist in consequence of State action.These, from an economic point of view, are not all so great as many Socialists, Anarchists, and Individualists imagine, at least in England.The main advantage would be in disabusing the public mind of the opposite superstition that State interference is very good and absolutely necessary. The fact is that it is no good at all.[69]
Tucker's reaction to all of Fisher's economic writings is to be found in his remarks in a column headlined "Anarchism and Children" written in 1895: "Pat Collins, the witty Democratic politician, once said of the late Prohibitionist leader Robert C. Pitman, that he would be a first-class man if he could only let rum alone.And I always think to myself, when I read the writings of Mr. J. Greevz Fisher in behalf of liberty, that he would be a first-class philosopher if he would only let money alone."[70]Tucker then went on to quote approvingly from an article by Fisher which appeared in Personal Rights in April 1895 dealing with the question of parental responsibility for the support of children.Mr. Fisher wrote in part:
it would be highly dangerous to attempt to make legal responsibilities generally and universally embrace all moral responsibilities, because, if it were attempted, the enforcement of every virtue and the suppression of every vice would become objects of legal coercion. . . .
Neglect is not attack. . . . If a person, male or female, alleging parentage beats, enslaves, or defrauds a child, the Individualist has a perfect right to interfere.He can voluntarily associate himself with the child in a mutual defence organization. . . . No title to guardianship by a claimant parent ought to be admitted when the alleged guardianship is inimical to the minor.Beyond this point if it is unsafe to take one step.Neglect can be better remedied by upholding liberty for anyone directly to supply the wants of the neglected.It cannot be safely dealt with by attempts of a third party to force someone, supposed to be responsible, to undertake the duty.[71]
Tucker then quoted from the lament of the Personal Rights editor, J. H. Levy, who noted that Fisher's argument was not, in fact, individualistic but rather anarchistic.Tucker, himself, had earlier written in favor of "The assumption is that we must not interfere to prevent neglect, but only to repress positive invasion."[72] Tucker still maintained that "no person, parent or not, may be rightfully compelled to support any helpless being, of whatever age or circumstance, unless he had made that being helpless by some invasive act."[73]
Subsequently, Tucker revised his position and logic on the question of parental responsibility and eventually concluded that the mother must own her children until the day that they reach maturity and self-emancipation."[74]His final statement of his position was found in his editorial "L'Enfant Terrible":
I can see no clearer property title in the world than that of the mother to the fruit of her womb, unless she has otherwise disposed of it by contract. . . . The change, then, which my opinion has undergone consists simply in the substitution of certainty for doubt as to the non-invasive character of parental cruelty--a substitution which involves the conclusion that parental cruelty is not to he prohibited, since third parties have not to consider the danger of disaster to organisms [children] that are outside the limits of social protection.[75]
In the same issue of Liberty, J. Greevz Fisher had a letter published in which he expressed his opposition to Tucker's conception of "children as chattels."Fisher pointed out that "the supposition of the chatteldom of the child, if based upon the utility, excellence and propriety of parental control, surely implies, among its benefits an advantage to the child."Thus during the whole period of parental control, the parent is not an owner at all, but rather a "trustee", in the legal jargon Fisher used.Fisher and other critics of Tucker's position pointed out that if the mother were owner of the child, she could kill her child, "as a man may kill a horse," or even throw her baby into the fire.[76]
Fisher was only one of several English individualists who claimed that the child was a self-owner who during its early years fell under the guardianship of its mother or parents.William Gilmour, the Scottish individualist, thought "guardianship, not ownership, is the real question at issue."[77]John Badcock, in his letter "On the Status of the Child," maintained that parents are the natural guardians of their children."But," he claimed, "guardian is not synonymous with owner, and, while guardianship is necessary for the child,--varying in quantity with the child's development,--ownership is quite an intrusion, as it is in all slavery."[78]Tucker expressed his opposition to the concept of guardianship or trusteeship. "I disclaim, however, any share in the belief which Mr. Badcock supposes me to hold in common with him that parents are the natural guardians of their offspring.I do not see why he supposes me to believe this, for not only is guardianship, as he says, not synonymous with ownership, but it is flatly contradictory of it. . . . Guardianship implies responsibility.In ownership there is no such responsibility. As I maintain that the mother is the owner of her child, of course I deny that she is guardian of her child."[79]
John Badcock, Jr. was the author of Slaves to Duty, a lecture which he delivered in London in 1894.Although he and Tucker disagreed on the children issue, they held nearly identical ethical theories resting on egoism as illustrated by Tucker's report of Badcock's lecture.
In this lecture Mr. Badcock lays the spook of duty most effectively. He takes up, one by one, the various kinds of duties--political, social, marital, filial, etc.--discusses them as to their merits and demerits, and demonstrates that the subordination of self on the part of the individual to their requirements prevents him from appreciating the full value of existence and realizing the promises it originally holds out. In the place of duty Mr. Badcock puts--nothing, "as superstitions never want replacing," but simply counsels people to study where their true and lasting interests lie and to turn all their energies to the furtherance of these regardless of codes, moral and political.[80]
Badcock and his English individualist friends displayed their contempt for society when they founded the Legitimation League in 1892 or 1893.J. H. Levy, J. Greevz Fisher, Donisthorpe, Badcock, along with Gladys and Oswald Dawson were all originally involved with the League.Its stated purpose was "to create machinery for acknowledging offspring born out of wedlock, and to secure for them equal rights with legitimate children."[81]In 1893, Fisher published a pamphlet entitled "Illegitimate Children: An Inquiry into their Personal Rights and a Plea for the Abolition of Illegitimacy."Wordsworth Donisthorpe published a review of this pamphlet in Liberty in 1894.[82] In 1897, according to Liberty, the League took on "A New Departure" as described by William Gilmour: "The Legitimation League, of London, which has had a somewhat passive existence since its formation four years ago, has now entered upon a 'new crusade'. . .viz., the advocacy of the principle of sexual freedom, or freedom in sexual relationships."Gilmour reported that Fisher and Donisthorpe had left the league, but that "Oswald Dawson, George Bedorough, Louie Bedorough, Seymour, Badcock, Rockell, and Wastall are still within its ranks."[83]Henry Seymour became editor of its journal, The Adult: A Journal for the Advancement of Freedom in Sexual Relationships, which had a short-lived existence during the late 1890's.[84]
Seymour had an interesting career as an anarchist, and fortunately a record of his early years in the movement has been preserved.His introduction to Tucker and Liberty was partly coincidental:
I chanced to meet Dr. Willard Knowleton Dyer and Sarah E. Holmes, who were travelling through Europe and temporarily staying at this resort [where Seymour had opened a "Science Library of advanced literature"]. They were enthusiastic in introducing the Boston Liberty, edited by Benj. R. Tucker, to my notice.Here was solid stuff, I thought, and not long elapsed before 1 was one of Liberty's agents, and some time after published an English edition of Tucker's translation of Bakunin's God and the State.I remember, also, at this time, I happened across an old copy of Edmund Burke's Vindication of Natural Society, which I sent to Tucker who promptly reprinted this gem as a classic introduction to the study of Anarchism.[85]
Seymour then recounts how he began publishing The Anarchist in March 1885."It set forth my own profession of faith,--almost identical with that of Liberty--and contained original contributions by such notable writers as Henry Appleton, George Bernard Shaw, and Elisee Reclus, with whom I had made contacts."[86]Eventually an English Anarchist Circle was formed among the many native and foreign anarchists in London, the most prominent of them being Peter Kropotkin. "The circle could not be squared," wrote Seymour, and due to the differing temperaments and philosophic outlooks, the group disbanded. Seymour continued to publish The Anarchist and then The Revolutionary Review, until he went bankrupt.Seymour had wide connections in English anarchist circles and "had good relations with Malatesta, Tochatti (editor of the London Liberty), A. Tarn (editor of the Herald of Anarchy), Robert Harding, the passive-resistance Anarchist; and also met Lucy Parsons, Emma Goldman, Josephine Tilton, Lillian Harman, Sebastian Faure, Louise Michel, Bernard Lazare, Benj. R. Tucker and Mrs. Tucker with their bright little daughter, Oriole, when they severally came to London on various occasions."[87]
Another aspect of the individualist anarchist movement in London during the last decades of the nineteenth century and the first decade of the twentieth was the Personal Rights Association.The extensive discussions between its secretary, J. H. Levy, and Auberon Herbert over compulsory taxation have already been examined.The Personal Rights Association has an interesting background and stems almost directly from the activities of a late Victorian reformer, Josephine Butler.A critic has described her as "the single individual most responsible for the spread of syphilis in Europe and perhaps the Josephine Butler was largely responsible for sparking the campaigns in England which led to the repeal of the Contagious Disease Acts.In 1864, the first of three Contagious Disease laws was passed by Parliament which made provisions for the surgical examination of prostitutes and for their confinement in "lock" hospitals if found diseased.The Act was limited to areas around eleven military garrisons and naval stations.The second Act of 1866 required prostitutes in these army towns to submit to medical examinations at least once every twelve months.A consolidating act was passed in 1868.In short the Contagious Disease Acts attempted to introduce in England the continental methods of regulating prostitution.[89]
Two distinct schools existed within the movement opposed to the Contagious Disease Acts. "For the policy, condemned by both alike, of regulating vice primarily in the interest of the physical health of vicious men, one desired to substitute the measures of vigorous suppression directed against men and women alike, while the other was chiefly concerned to protect poor and friendless women from being blackmailed and harassed by the police in the name of public decency, and was for leaving all forms of vice which did not involve force or fraud to be combatted by voluntary and non-coercive agencies."[90]Josephine Butler's organized activities against the Contagious Disease Acts began in 1869 or 1870, with the formation of the Ladies National Association for Repeal of the Contagious Disease Acts.Mrs. Butler was not a suppressionist, but rather believed in voluntary efforts to deal with the problem. In March 1871, she was on the organizing committee of The Vigilance Association for the Defence of Personal Rights and for the Amendment of the Law Wherein It Is Injurious to Women.[91]The membership of this latter organization reflects its origins in the Contagious Disease Acts controversy as well as in its overall anti-statist inclinations. For example, "while the radicals of the organization were caught up in the attempt to abolish state regulation of prostitution, they had also become exercised by a remarkably similar issue, compulsory vaccination."[92]During the years 1881 to 1886, The Vigilance Association restyled itself and its purposes.J. H. Levy, who had been connected with the organization since 1878, was largely responsible for these changes.[93]
Under Levy's leadership, the group became even more anti-statist.Beginning about 1881 such individualists as Donisthorpe, Herbert, and W. C. Crofts became involved in the organization.As the campaign for the repeal of the Contagious Disease Acts approached success (repeal was passed by Parliament in 1886), the two groups within The Vigilance Association (the coercive suppressionists and the non-coercive persuasionists) splintered. The suppressionists formed their own new organization called The National Vigilance Association for the Repression of Vice and Public Immorality. The persuasionists, claiming that the new group had "filched from us our good name," changed the name of the original Vigilance Association to The Personal Rights Association.[94] Its organ, successively titled The Personal Rights Journal, Personal Rights, and lastly The Individualist, was published for over thirty years by Levy.[95] Through this medium, Levy "worked on the frontiers of liberal individualism in pursuit of the full application of the classical ideal of perfect equality before the law."He "also worked in the neglected areas of personal rights, pioneering in lunacy law reform, participating in the anti-vivisection campaign and thereby extending liberal individualism. . . to its ultimate limits: the world of the helpless and the animal kingdom."[96]
At least two supporters of the Personal Rights Association were involved in other anti-statist organizations.Wordsworth Donisthorpe was one of the two co-founders of the State Resistance Union (1880), which was the predecessor of the Liberty and Property Defence League (1882). Donisthorpe edited his own individualist journal, Jus, from January 1885 until March 1888.[97]Eventually Donisthorpe resigned from the Liberty and Property Defence League, because he was not satisfied with its limited activities.[98]Donisthorpe's cousin, W. C. Crofts, remained administrator and secretary of the League until his death in 1894.Both he and Crofts tried to keep liberty, rather than property, to the fore, but it seemed to Donisthorpe that the League was more interested in defending the privileges of property.[99]
"Among the individualists an exotic variety of organizations" abounded.[100] Similarly there existed a wide range of opinions among those calling themselves individualists or individualist anarchists.Despite the differences between Tucker and the group of English individualists we have examined in this paper, all of them could probably subscribe to Tucker's eloquent summation of his own creed, entitled "Woes of An Anarchist," written in response to Wordsworth Donisthorpe's essay of 1890: "there are some troubles from which mankind can never escape. . . . They [the anarchists] have never claimed that liberty will bring perfection; they simply say that its results are vastly preferable to those that follow from authority. . . . As a choice of blessings, liberty is the greater; as a choice of evils, liberty is the smaller. Then liberty always says the Anarchist:No use of force except against the invader."[101]

No comments:

Post a Comment